Philosophy

What John Stuart Mill got wrong about freedom

Mill's famous vision of freedom is compelling—but of its own time. Instead of focussing on the individual, we should seek freedom through our responsibilities to others

January 02, 2019
Mill's vision of freedom made sense in the context of Victorian Britain, but less so in our age of increasing loneliness and anxiety. Photo: PA
Mill's vision of freedom made sense in the context of Victorian Britain, but less so in our age of increasing loneliness and anxiety. Photo: PA
You can tell what a society values by what it goes to war over. In the 17th century, we fought our wars over religion. In the 19th, it was empire. In the 20th and 21st, we fight our wars over freedom—either defending our own or trying to export our version of it to other parts of the world.

We tend, of course, to assume we know what freedom is: the liberty to do what we like as long as don’t harm other people. But we rarely know how recent such a view of freedom is.

John Stuart Mill—child prodigy, colonial administrator and philosopher—is one of the primary architects of our contemporary ideas of freedom. Published soon after his death, his book On Liberty, was, in his words, an exploration of the “nature and limits of the power that can legitimately be exercised by society over the individual.” Mill famously argues that the only valid reason for interfering with another person’s liberty of action is to protect them from physical harm. It is never justifiable to interfere with another person’s freedom to ensure their happiness, wisdom or well-being because that is to determine what that person’s well-being is. Freedom is defined as liberty of conscience, thought, feeling and opinion, as “liberty of tastes and pursuits … doing as we like … without impediment from our fellow creatures, so long as what we do does not harm them.” 

Mill is one of the great champions of nonconformity in thought and action. Even if just one person held a particular opinion while everyone else in the world held the opposite, there would be no justification in silencing that one voice. For Mill, one of the main ingredients of social progress is freedom from the traditions and customs imposed by others, which restricts the cultivation of individuality, which in turn “is one of the leading essentials of well-being.” Individual liberty is vital, not just for the sake of the individual, but for the sake of human progress. Without it there will be no originality or genius, no new discoveries or innovation. Civilisation cannot advance without a degree of individual freedom which encourages spontaneous expression, and the development of new thoughts and ideas unconstrained by the patterns of the past.

It is a powerful argument. On Liberty is full of the fear of Victorian conformity—the individualist’s reaction to a stifling society with a high degree of social control. It is very much a book of its time, assuming the cultural superiority of the modern age. It also breathes an elitism that looks down on the mediocrity of what it calls “average men.”

But more than that, there is, I think, a deeper flaw in its way of thinking about freedom. If freedom is essentially my liberty to say or do what I like, as long as I don’t tread on the toes of my neighbour, then my neighbour becomes at best a limitation; at worst, a threat to my freedom. There may be all kinds of things I want to do—play my music loud on a summer’s night, or drive my car at 100 mph on a quiet suburban road—but I can’t because I might disturb my neighbour’s peace or risk crashing into an oncoming bus. Even worse, my neighbour might want to play her music too loud for me, or drive her car too fast in my direction, thus invading my personal space.

This approach keeps the peace between us but at the cost of making us see each other either as irritating limitations to our desires—which of course define our self-chosen goals in life—or threats to our own precious autonomy.

The German sociologist Harmut Rosa argues that “the ethical imperative that guides modern subjects is not a particular or substantive definition of the good life, but the aspiration to acquire the resources necessary or helpful for leading one.” In other words, in the individualised world imagined by Mill, we are all left to dream our own dreams, choose our own ambitions, and become caught up in the fight to acquire the money, rights, friends, looks, health, and knowledge that will enable us to get to our self-chosen destination. It therefore makes us competitors with each other, not only seeing each other as rivals in this race for resources, but also as potential threats who might stand in the way of our freedom to pursue our dreams. 

There is however another, older, view of freedom. This alternative is rooted more in character and virtue than in individualised personal goals. Found in classical literature, this version sees liberty not as freedom from the limitations and social expectations that stop us following our self-chosen desires, but freedom from the “passions.” The Greeks viewed the soul as like a ship which should sail serenely towards the harbour of such virtues as prudence, courage and temperance. It was guided on this journey by paideia—or education in virtue—yet was at the same time buffeted by the winds of irrational and destructive impulses such as envy, anger or lust that threaten to blow it off course. For them, our passionate desires are not the sacrosanct moral guide to our true selves, but are a distraction from the true path of virtue.

This version was developed further by Christian thinkers such as St Paul, St Augustine and St Thomas Aquinas. For them, true liberty is freedom from anything that would stop us becoming the person we were created to be: someone capable of love for what is outside ourselves—for God and our neighbour. True liberty is, therefore, freedom from internal urges such as greed, laziness or pride that turn us in upon ourselves rather than outwards towards God and each other. It is also freedom from external forces such as the grinding poverty that dangles the temptation to steal in order to survive, or an economy that constantly tells us that the secret of life is acquiring more things. It is not so much freedom for ourselves, but freedom from ourselves: freedom from self-centred desires, or the crippling self-absorption that makes us think only of our own interests. It is freedom to create the kind of society where we are more concerned with our neighbours’ well-being than our own.

In this view of freedom, my neighbour becomes not a limitation or a threat, but a gift—someone without whom I cannot become someone capable of the primary virtue of love. Putting it bluntly, if I am to become someone capable of other-centred love, I need someone to practice on! It offers a vision of society where you might begin to trust other people to look after your needs, because they are looking out for yours as you look out for theirs in turn.

It is also a vision of freedom that arguably delivers personal happiness better than the libertarian view. Becoming the kind of person who has learnt, as St Paul once put it, to “look not to your own interests, but to the interests of others” is a recipe for healthy relationships and contentment rather than the increasing isolation of much modern life. Taking responsibility to look out for our neighbour’s needs is not therefore a constraint on our freedom but a means to it.

Mill may have had a point in the stifling conservatism of Victorian Britain, but in an age of increasing loneliness, isolation and anxiety, his view of freedom doesn’t help build good neighbourhoods, families or communities. We need a better version: one that brings us together, rather than driving us apart.